I.
Somewhere in his writings Leo Strauss remarks that the Jewish problem is the political problem in nuce.
This pregnant remark was meant to invite two sorts of reflections. One, the
most obvious, concerns the historical fate of world Jewry, from the biblical
age down through the Diaspora and the establishment of the state of Israel.
The other, less obvious, concerns the light that Judaism as a social fact
sheds on our understanding of politics more generally. Here Strauss had in
mind what he called the "theological-political problem," which he saw as
the unavoidable tension between political authority and divine revelation.
But the Jewish problem is significant in a third sense, too. For how nations
or civilizations cope with the existence of the Jews can, at certain historical
junctures, reveal political pathologies whose causes have little or nothing
to do with Judaism as such. There are periods when the acuteness of the Jewish
problem is a symptom of a deeper malaise in political life and political
ideas.
There is little doubt that contemporary Europe is passing through such
a moment. It is not the first. Throughout Europe's history there have been
periods in which a crisis in political ideas had important consequences for
Jews in their relations with other Europeans. The anti-Semitic persecutions
of the Middle Ages, which had many sources, also coincided with a disturbance
in European thinking about the relation between ecclesiastical power and
secular power, between the City of God and the City of Man. The emancipation
of the Jews in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries coincided with the
epochal shift from absolutism to theories of republicanism and democracy.
And the rejection of those Enlightenment political concepts in the late nineteenth
and early twentieth centuries in the name of nationalist, racialist, and
anti-modern ideals portended events that will shape Jewish consciousness
for all time.
Today Europeans find themselves living in what historians call a "saddle
period." One distinct age has passed, that of the Cold War, and an obscure
new one has begun. Looking back on the era just ended, one fact is especially
striking about the intellectual life of Western Europe, or "old Europe":
the omnipresence of political ideologies and passions, and the relative absence
of serious political thought, understood as disciplined and impartial reflection
about distinctly political experience. There were exceptions to this intellectual
collapse, and they are widely recognized and revered today: Isaiah Berlin
and Michael Oakeshott in Britain, Raymond Aron in France, Norberto Bobbio
in Italy, and perhaps a few others. But due to the overwhelming attraction
of Marxism and structuralism in all their variants, the influence of these
thinkers on wider intellectual discussions was actually quite limited in
this period. What was paradoxical about those schools was that they encouraged
political engagement while at the same time absorbing all thinking about
political experience into amorphous discussions of larger historical, economic,
or linguistic forces. The result was that political action intensified as
political thought atrophied.
Ý
iewed
in retrospect, the intellectual flight from political thought in Europe now
appears as a reaction to, and a means of coping with, the unique conditions
of the Cold War. After the disasters of the first half of the twentieth century,
Western European politics were put on ice--or at least some of the essential
questions were. Economies were reorganized, constitutions rewritten, parliaments
and parties reconstituted, social mores revised. But the most fundamental
issue for all modern nation-states--the issue of sovereignty--could not be
addressed, because neither the European community as a whole nor Western
European countries individually were fully sovereign. The concept of "sovereignty"
has been given many, even incompatible, meanings over the centuries, but
at its core is the notion of autonomy, which in political terms means the
capacity to defend oneself and, when necessary, to decide to wage war. In
this respect European nations were not sovereign during the Cold War. There
were good reasons why that was so, and why for decades Western European thinkers
were relieved not to have to think about such matters, and the United States
and NATO were relieved to do their thinking
for them. It was a prudent arrangement, but in the end it had unhealthy intellectual
consequences.
Those consequences have been on public display in two related spheres
since 1989. The most important is Continental thinking about the European
Union. In the early postwar decades, there was some inspiring talk about
a "United States of Europe," but as the decades wore on, the concept of "Europe"
came to have little meaning beyond economic cooperation. Over the past decade,
though, we have witnessed an extremely uncritical embrace of the idea of
Europe among Western European intellectuals generally, and its invocation
as a kind of charm against the most difficult political questions facing
the Continent today. There are many reasons for this, and they differ country
by country. In formerly fascist countries--Germany, Italy, Spain--the idea
of the nation-state remains in ill repute, while the blissfully undefined
notion of "Europe" inspires pacific, post-political hopes. In France, the
idea of Europe is generally seen not as a substitute for the nation but as
a tool for constraining German might on the Continent and American influence
from across the Atlantic. And for intellectuals in the smaller countries,
belonging to "Europe" means the hope of escaping cultural obscurity.
What Europe means as a distinctly political entity remains a mystery
to all involved. The wisest European commentators worry about this. They
are concerned about what is called the "democratic deficit" in the European
institutions of Brussels and Strasbourg. They also wonder how widely the
community can be extended, not only in economic terms but, as in the case
of Turkey, also in cultural ones. Yet serious reflection about the nature
of European sovereignty and its relation to national sovereignty is rare
these days, except among academic specialists. And so natural concerns about
the future of the nation, and the public debate about it, have been left
to xenophobes and chauvinists, of whom there are more than a few in every
European country.
It is nothing less than extraordinary that the idea of the nation-state
as the locus of political action and political reflection fell so quickly
and so silently into oblivion among Western European thinkers in our time.
The great exception that proves the rule is France, where passionate appeals
to the Gaullist tradition of national autonomy have run up against equally
passionate appeals to European and international cooperation, leading to
the kind of diplomatic incoherence that was recently put on display at the
United Nations. There are some understandable reasons for this development,
too. After all, one of the important lessons that Europeans have drawn from
their twentieth-century history is that nationalism is always a danger, and
that it can infect and eventually destroy liberal democracy.
Ý
ut
what are the serious alternatives to the nation-state as a form of political
life? Historically speaking, we know what they are: tribe and empire, neither
of which Europeans wish to restore as their preferred form of political association.
Between those extremes there have been short-lived experiments with small,
defenseless republics and weak, ephemeral leagues or alliances. But for more
than two centuries the fate of decent and humane politics in Europe has been
tied to that of the nation-state as the dominant form of European political
life. And we can see why. If a moderately sized political entity is to attract
the loyalty and the commitment of its citizens, it must find a way to bind
them together; and among the ties it finds ready to hand are those of language,
religion, and culture, broadly understood. Yes, those ties are artifacts
of history, subject to manipulation and "invention"; they are not brute facts.
But they are, politically speaking, extremely useful inventions, given that
only the rarest of states could generate those ties by civic means alone.
(Not even the United States or Switzerland manages to do so.) One of the
long-standing puzzles of politics is how to wed political attachment (which
is particular) to political decency (which knows no borders). The nation-state
has been the best modern means discovered so far of squaring the circle,
opening a political space for both reasonable reflection and effective action.
It may be that the European Union will turn out to be something new,
and beneficent, on the European political landscape. I am skeptical, but
it is possible. What is certainly clear, though, is that European institutions
have not yet reached that stage, nor do they have the kind of public legitimacy
that would permit them to be the focus of political life in terms of action
or attachment, let alone reflection. So what is the focus of intellectual
reflection on European politics today? The nation is still there, but it
must lurk in the background, unacknowledged. To paraphrase the wicked Joseph
de Maistre, I have never yet met a "European" intellectual: I have met French
intellectuals, Italian intellectuals, and German intellectuals, and I have
heard it rumored that there are English intellectuals; but there are no "European"
intellectuals. Writers and thinkers still use their national languages, they
still absorb themselves in parochial national debates, and they still take
rather characteristic national stands on certain issues. Yet all these realities
notwithstanding, the idea of the nation-state as a distinct form of political
life is simply not an important theme for Western European thinkers at this
time. They have, thankfully, stopped trying to answer the question of whether
a nation has an "essence"--Renan's famous question, qu'est-ce qu'une nation? But they have also, more disturbingly, ceased to think seriously about the political function of nation-states--ý quoi sert la nation?
Ý
he
debacle of the Balkans in the late 1990s, and Western Europe's painfully
slow response to the threats of political collapse and even genocide there,
had something to do with this intellectual paralysis. For the first time
in fifty years, European thinkers faced a military crisis to which they could
have responded, and probably should have responded, without American assistance.
But who exactly was supposed to respond? The nation-states of Europe, acting
alone or in concert? Or "Europe," the European community, conceived as a
coherent political entity? Many European intellectuals were opposed to any
intervention, on different grounds, and sometimes on purely pacifist ones,
as in Germany. A number of quite prominent thinkers, especially in France,
called for intervention on humanitarian grounds, though without much caring
what sort of political entity handled the job. As German Foreign Minister
Joschka Fischer, one of the earliest and most vigorous supporters of intervention,
remarked in a recent interview, pan-European institutions simply are not
yet capable of handling these sorts of crises. And so the catastrophe in
the Balkans proceeded for a long time unimpeded. Europeans no longer think
of the nation-state as the sole place where foreign policy should be determined
and military means chosen, but they are not yet able to treat the European
Union as that place. As a result, they have generally ceased to think seriously
and responsibly about such matters.
It will be said by some intellectuals that that is because Europeans,
given their recent history, have discovered the need to regulate such matters
through international law and organizations. But this simply removes the
problem to a higher, and far less stable, plane. If the sovereignty and the
political legitimacy of the European Union is a complicated business, the
moral and political authority of the United Nations or a World Criminal Court
or non-governmental organizations is infinitely more so. It is simply a fantasy
to think that the perennial problems of politics can be dissolved through
progressive juridification or humanitarian aid, which is what some very serious
European thinkers, notably Jurgen Habermas, clearly have in mind. The danger
is not that thinking so might make it true; it is that no amount of thinking
ever will. Wars that involve European nations will happen, sovereignty will
be exercised--and European thinkers will simply be less prepared to understand
both of those inevitabilities if the fantasy of escaping them retains its
grip on the European mind.
II.
It is against the backdrop of this intellectual crisis of sovereignty
that the contemporary "Jewish question" in Europe must be seen. For centuries
that question was, broadly speaking, one of inclusion: what sorts of people
could be citizens and under what conditions, whether religion mattered, whether
differences could be tolerated. This form of the problem still exists in
Europe, though today Muslims are more likely to be the object of prejudice
and violence than Jews are. The battle for toleration as an idea has largely
been won; the challenges now are to put it into practice and to understand
its limits within each national context.
It is not the idea of tolerance that is in crisis in Europe today, it
is the idea of the nation-state, and the related concepts of sovereignty
and the use of force. And these ideas have also affected European intellectual
attitudes toward world Jewry, and specifically toward Israel. Here there
is an extraordinary paradox that deserves to be savored. For centuries Jews
were the stateless people and suffered at the hands of Europeans who were
deeply rooted in their own nations. The early Zionists, from Hess to Herzl,
drew a very simple lesson from this experience: that Jews could not live
safely or decently until they had their own state. Those who claim today
that the state of Israel is the brainchild of nineteenth-century European
thought are not wrong; this is hardly a secret. But the point is often made
with sinister intent, as if to suggest that Israel and the Zionist enterprise
more generally represent some kind of political atavism that enlightened
Europeans should spurn. Once upon a time, the Jews were mocked for not having
a nation-state. Now they are criticized for having one.
And not just any nation-state, but one whose founding is still fresh
in living memory. All political foundings, without exception, are morally
ambiguous enterprises, and Israel has not escaped these ambiguities. Two
kinds of fools and bigots refuse to see this: those who deny or explain away
the Palestinian suffering caused by Israel's founding, and those who treat
that suffering as the unprecedented consequence of a uniquely sinister ideology.
The moral balance-sheet of Israel's founding, which is still being composed,
must be compared to those of other nations at their conception, not to the
behavior of other nations after their existence was secured. And it is no
secret that Israel must still defend itself against nations and peoples who
have not reconciled themselves to its existence--an old, but now forgotten,
European practice. Many Western European intellectuals, including those whose
toleration and even affection for Jews cannot be questioned, find all this
incomprehensible. The reason is not anti-Semitism nor even anti-Zionism in
the usual sense. It is that Israel is, and is proud to be, a nationstate--the
nation-state of the Jews. And that is profoundly embarrassing to post-national
Europe.
Consider the issue from the perspective of a young European who might
have grown up in the postwar world. From his first day of school he would
have been taught the following lesson about twentieth-century history: that
all its disasters can be traced to nationalism, militarism, and racism. He
might even have learned that Jews were the main victims of these political
pathologies, and would have developed a certain sympathy for their plight.
But as he grew up he would have begun to learn about contemporary Israel,
mainly in light of the conflict with the Palestinians, and his views would
probably have begun to change. From his own history he would have concluded
that nations are suspect entities, that the distinction they make between
insider and outsider is immoral, and that military force is to be forsworn.
He would then have likely concluded that contemporary Israel violates all
these maxims: it is proudly independent, it distinguishes between Jew and
non-Jew, it defends itself without apology. The charges that Zionism is racism,
or that Israel is behaving like the Nazis in the occupied territories, undoubtedly
have roots in anti-Semitism; but frustration with the very existence of Israel
and the way it handles its challenges has a more proximate cause in European
intellectual life. That cause is the crisis in the European idea of a nation-state.
Anyone who pays close attention to how the Israeli-Palestinian conflict
is handled in the European press, and even in intellectual journals, will
see this frustration expressed on a regular basis. I do not think this can
be ascribed solely to European pro-Arabism, just as American press coverage
cannot be attributed entirely to the feelings of Jewish Americans for Israel.
I am convinced that at a deeper level the differences have something to do
with the way Americans and Europeans think about political life more generally
today, differences that Robert Kagan has highlighted in his powerful little
book Of Paradise and Power.
While it may not be true that Americans are uniformly Martian (Woodrow Wilson
was not Belgian, after all), Kagan is correct that the European consensus
today, from left to right, is thoroughly Venutian in spirit. This causes
occasional friction with the United States, but it is a source of fundamental
disaccord with the Zionist project. For Zionists today are indeed from Mars,
par la force des choses.
Even European sympathy for the Palestinian people, which is understandable
and honorable, has an oddly apolitical quality to it. One would think that
those concerned about the future of the Palestinians, and not simply about
their present suffering, would be thinking chiefly about how to remove them
from tutelage to terrorist and fundamentalist organizations, and how to establish
a legitimate, law-abiding, and liberal political authority that could negotiate
in good faith with Israel and manage Palestinian domestic affairs in a transparent
manner. But there is almost no intellectual awareness in Europe of the political
obstacles to peace that exist among the Palestinians, nor has there been
much encouragement of political reform. To judge by what is written, the
European fantasy of the future Middle East is not of decent, liberal nation-states
living side by side in peace, but of some sort of post-national, post-political
order growing up under permanent international supervision. Not Menachem
Begin and Anwar Sadat shaking hands, but Hans Blix zipping around Palestine
in his little truck.
Anyone schooled in the history of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
is well aware of the political pathologies of the nation-state and the idolatry
that it invites. The legitimacy of the nation-state should not be confused
with the idolatry of the nation-state. But for many in Western Europe today,
learning the grim lesson of modern history has also brought with it a forgetting
of all the long-standing problems that the nation-state, as a modern form
of political life, managed to solve. The Zionist tradition knows what those
problems were. It remembers what it was to be stateless, and the indignities
of tribalism and imperialism. It remembers the wisdom of borders and the
need for collective autonomy to establish self-respect and to demand respect
from others. It recognizes that there is a cost, a moral cost, to defending
a nation-state and exercising sovereignty; but it also recognizes that the
cost is worth paying, given the alternatives. Eventually Western Europeans
will have to re-learn these lessons, which are, after all, the lessons of
their own pre-modern history. Until they do, the mutual incomprehension regarding
Israel between Europeans and Jews committed to Zionism will remain deep.
There is indeed a new Jewish problem in Europe, because there is a new political
problem in Europe.